Lon
Well-known Member
- Location
- Central California
Charles Darwin outlined a different way of thinking about ethics, and we are now able to articulate more fully the hints he offered. Ethics emerges as a human phenomenon, permanently unfinished. To adopt this perspective provides a different perspective on many questions that now confront us.
We became fully human when we were able to find ways of inhibiting tendencies to socially disruptive action and ways of reinforcing our altruistic capacities. Practices of punishment may well have played a role at early stages of the process. The crucial step, however, consisted in internalizing the check on our behavior. We became able to formulate rules for ourselves, or to remind ourselves of exemplary cases of conduct: we invented a crude system of ethics.
Lets propose an ethics question and see how we resolve it.
"Greed is good".
Agree or disagree.
Give your reasons.
Part of the answer is to appreciate a great insight of Plato’s. To say that ethics is founded in the command of God – or the dictates of Reason, for that matter – doesn’t help. Not every command should be obeyed, and it is crucial that the source of the command be a good one. Thus there must be some prior basis of goodness, antecedent to the source of the command, against which that source measures up. Failure to think in terms of that prior standard pervades the testimonies, offered in courtrooms from Jerusalem to Johannesburg, of those who protested that they were only following the orders of their powerful superiors. That sort of evasion is no more successful when the putative “superior” invoked is powerful beyond human comprehension.
Off the top of my head I would think that greed must be bad and not good because greed is selfish and selfishness is not good
Neo-Darwinists like Richard Dawkins would argue that greed is natural - he wrote the book "The Selfish Gene" that posits that evolution is all about genes, for a better word, wanting to replicate themselves, and this is what drives human and animal behaviour. Can natural behaviour ever be declared bad?
Thinking about an age old ethical dilemma:When "natural" behavior leads to actions that hurt others, absolutely
I don't remember the motive of the Colorado theatre shooter's behaviour so I'll substitute another example into the same basic question.Is it natural to murder others out of anger or greed? Was the Colorado theatre shooter's behavior natural to him? If so, does that make it "natural" in this sense? May be so, but certainly bad
Throw a rock through your neighbor's window. Expect to get one back. You help him plant, he helps you harvest, you both eat.
You don't steal his stuff. He doesn't steal yours. You both get a good nights sleep. Its not rocket science.
There will always be bad behavior by individuals for a number of reasons, but what we call good is good, because it works for us.
Measure for measure is seen in all primitive societies, often referred to as payback. Rough justice at best and totally reactionary. Ethics must be founded on principles and reasoning. Many a woman, and less frequently men, have been killed because some villager has died of unknown causes and sorcery is blamed. It is quite natural in some societies to think that someone is to blame for every death. Definitely not rocket science, but is it bad if it works for the tribe?
What if we are not talking about individuals? What if we are talking about corporations, or nations ?
"You don't steal his stuff" ? What about stealing another company's customers by dropping your prices below production cost until he's bankrupt, or capturing the markets of another country by using subsidies to undercut their exports? It certainly works for the winners. Is it still rocket science?
Playing the Devil's Advocate here.
Thinking about an age old ethical dilemma:
It is natural for people to engage in sexual behaviour.
It is natural for a woman to become pregnant from sexual behaviour.
Marriage is not a natural state - it is a human construct, mostly aimed at securing inheritances.
So, a woman becomes pregnant and her husband may or may not be the father.
The ethical question is should she tell him and hurt his feelings or remain silent to protect her unborn child.
What harm will result from either choice?
How does she decide which action produces the least harm to herself, her husband and her child?
I don't remember the motive of the Colorado theatre shooter's behaviour so I'll substitute another example into the same basic question.
Is it natural to kill others out of revenge? Was the United States justified in dropping the second atom bomb on Japan or the British justified in carpet bombing the city of Dresden in the dying days of the war ? Is it natural to want to obliterate an enemy that has killed huge numbers of your tribe? If so, is it also bad?
Please keep the discussion secular.
Off the top of my head I would think that greed must be bad and not good because greed is selfish and selfishness is not good
More here: http://utilitarianphilosophy.com/definition.eng.htmlUtilitarianism is mainly characterized by two elements: happiness and consequentialism. Utilitarian happiness is the biggest happiness which (supposetly) every human being looks for. In utilitarianism everything useful to happiness is good. Therefore, the name of the doctrine is utilitarianism, based on the principle of utility. Utility is found in every thing which contributes to the happiness of every rational being. The criterion of good and evil is balanced between individual's happiness and the happiness of the community, "each counting in an equal way" (Bentham, Introduction in the principles of morality and legislation).
Consequentialism in utilitarianism is in the fact that an action must be judged for its consequences on the happiness of the largest number. That is: my search for happiness stops when it decreases the happiness of another individual or the happiness of the largest number, of the society or the community. As personal freedom is considered in respect of the freedom of other individuals and of the community, my freedom stops when it diminishes the freedom of another individual or the well-being of the society. We could say that utilitarianism is the continuation of Roman legislation, and its modern aspect is shown in the fact that utilitarianism adds an economical, legislative and political dimension to an ethical concept, that of happiness and well-being. The modern aspect of the doctrine will evolve throughout the 19th century, with Bentham, Mill and Sidgwick who succeeds in giving to this doctrine a practical and rational dimension which we can find in our modern society, in economics, politics and ethics.
"The continuing vitality of the greatest happiness system is not difficult to understand – it embodies a very natural and compelling model of rationality. This model, which dominates much of contemporary economics (as well as decision theory, "cost-benefit analysis", and "public choice theory") sees rational action as an attempt to maximise net utility (i.e. the result of summing the benefits and costs and subtracting the latter from the former). This view, which is frequently called "means-end" rationality, goes back (at least) to Aristotle. In the Nicomachean Ethics Aristotle asserts that "we cannot deliberate about ends but only about the means by which ends can be attained." If we assume, with Aristotle, that happiness is the "highest good attainable by action," and hence the aim of politics, we get something very like Bentham's view. Indeed it is tempting, and not implausible, to interpret philosophers as different as Adam Smith and Chairman Mao as agreeing that the goal of social institutions is the maximization of realizing that end.
Of course philosophers who share this vision of the proper function of social institutions like law and morality may differ on more than the best methods to attain it, as Aristotle noted, there is widespread agreement that happiness is the goal, but considerable disagreement as to what constitutes happiness. For Bentham the answer is simple: happiness is just pleasure and absence of pain. The value (or disvalue) of a pleasure (or pain) depends only on its intensity and duration, and can (at least in principle) be quantified precisely. Given this, we can reconstruct one line of Bentham's argument for the principle of UTILITY as something like the following:
- The good of a society is the sum of happiness of the individuals in that society.
- The purpose of morality is promotion of the good of society.
- A moral principle is ideal if and only if universal conformity to it would maximize the good of society.
- Universal conformity to the principle of UTILITY ("Act always so as to maximize total net balance of pleasures and pains") would maximize the good of society
The following is taken from the website of The Council of Secular Humanism. It pretty well summarizes my own thoughts on ethical behavior.
The Common Moral Decencies
The common moral decencies are widely shared. They are essential to the survival of any human community. Meaningful coexistence cannot occur if they are consistently flouted. Handed down through countless generations, they are recognized throughout the world by friends and relatives, colleagues and coworkers, the native-born and immigrant, as basic rules of social intercourse. They are the foundation of moral education and are taught in the family and the schools. They express the elementary virtues of courtesy, politeness, and empathy so essential for living together; indeed, they are the very basis of civilized life itself. The common moral decencies are transcultural in their range and have their roots in generic human needs. They no doubt grow out of the long evolutionary struggle for survival and may even have some sociobiological basis, though they may be lacking in some individuals or societies since their emergence depends upon certain preconditions of moral and social development. Here is a list of some of the decencies:
First are the moral decencies that involve personal integrity, that is, telling the truth, not lying or being deceitful; being sincere, candid, frank, and free of hypocrisy; keeping one’s promises, honoring pledges, living up to agreements; and being honest, avoiding fraud or skullduggery.
Second is trustworthiness. We manifest loyalty to our relatives, friends, and coworkers, and we should be dependable, someone they can count on, reliable, and responsible.
Third are the decencies of benevolence, which involve manifesting goodwill and noble intentions toward other human beings and having a positive concern for them. It means the lack of malice (nonmalfeasance), avoiding doing harm to other persons or their property: We should not kill or rob; inflict physical violence or injury; or be cruel, abusive, or vengeful. In the sexual domain it means that we should not force our sexual passions on others and should seek mutual consent between adults. It means that we have an obligation to be beneficent; that is, kind, sympathetic, compassionate. We should lend a helping hand to those in distress and try to decrease their pain and suffering and contribute positively to their welfare.
Fourth is the principle of fairness. We should show gratitude and appreciation for those who are deserving of it. A civilized community will hold people accountable for their deeds, insisting that those who wrong others do not go completely unpunished and perhaps must make reparations to the aggrieved. This also involves the principle of justice and equality in society. Tolerance is also a basic moral decency: We should allow other individuals the right to their beliefs, values, and styles of life, even though they may differ from our own. We may not agree with them, but each individual is entitled to his convictions as long as he does not harm others or prevent them from exercising their rights. We should try to cooperate with others, seeking to negotiate differences peacefully without resorting to hatred or violence.
These common moral decencies express general principles and rules. Though individuals or nations may deviate from practicing them, they nonetheless provide general parameters by which to guide our conduct. They are not absolute and may at times conflict; we may have to establish priorities between them. They need not be divinely ordained to have moral force, for they are tested in the last analysis by their consequences in practice. Morally developed human beings accept these principles and attempt to live by them because they understand that some personal moral sacrifices may be necessary to avoid conflict in living and working together. Practical moral wisdom thus recognizes the obligatory nature of responsible conduct.